Modélisation de valeurs humaines : le cas des vertus dans les jeux hédoniques

Modélisation de valeurs humaines : le cas des vertus dans les jeux hédoniques

Thibaut Vallée Grégory Bonnet Thibault de Swarte  

Normandie Université, UNICAEN, GREYC, CNRS UMR 6072

Normandie Université, UNICAEN, GREYC, CNRS UMR 6072

IMT Atlantique, Idea Lab LASCO-IMT, UBL, F-35576 Cesson-Sévigné Cedex

Corresponding Author Email: 
thibaut.vallee@unicaen.fr; gregory.bonnet@unicaen.fr; thibault.deswarte@imt-atlantique.fr
Page: 
519-546
|
DOI: 
https://doi.org/10.3166/ria.32.519-546
Received: 
| |
Accepted: 
| | Citation

OPEN ACCESS

Abstract: 

In many applicative contexts, several autonomous artificial agents must interact, make decision and cooperate in a collective way. In those contexts, an agent must not only take into account ethical criterion to reach its goals but also need to decide how it will cooperate and how it will take the other agents’ goals into account. Thus, in this article, we are interested by modeling a virtue ethics, ie. which aims at supporting a cardinal moral value, for collective formation. To this end, we propose a new model of coalition formation, called deviation hedonic games, where each agent decides which coalition it will form according to a set of atomic behavioral rules. Then we show how those rules can be combined in order to represent a plurality of values. As examples, we model three values – liberty, altruism and hedonism – which allow us to characterize new solution concepts.

Keywords: 

coalitions, human values, multi-agent systems, virtue ethics

1. Introduction
2. État de l’art
3. Des jeux de déviations
4. Modéliser les valeurs humaines
5. Conclusion et perspectives
Remerciements
  References

Akerlof G. A. (1984). Gift exchange and efficiency-wage theory: Four views. The American Economic Review, vol. 74, no 2, p. 79–83.

Arkin R. (2009). Governing lethal behavior in autonomous robots. Chapman and Hall.

Aziz H., Brandt F., Harrenstein P. (2013). Pareto optimality in coalition formation. Games and Economic Behavior, vol. 82, p. 562 - 581.

Aziz H., Brandt F., Seedig H. G. (2011). Stable partitions in additively separable hedonic games. In 10th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 183–190.

Aziz H., Brandt F., Seedig H. G. (2013). Computing desirable partitions in additively separable hedonic games. Artificial Intelligence, vol. 195, p. 316–334.

Ballester C. (2004). NP-completeness in hedonic games. Games and Economic Behavior, vol. 49, no 1, p. 1–30.

Bardi A., Lee J., Hofmann-Towfigh N., Soutar G. (2009). The structure of intraindividual value change. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, vol. 97, no 5, p. 913-929.

Bardsley N. (2008). Dictator game giving: altruism or artefact? Experimental Economics, vol. 11, no 2, p. 122–133.

Batson C. D. (2014). The altruism question: Toward a social-psychological answer. Psychology Press.

Bench-Capon T. (2002). Agreeing to differ: modelling persuasive dialogue between parties with different values. Informal Logic, vol. 22, no 3, p. 231-245.

Berreby F., Bourgne G., Ganascia J.-G. (2017). A declarative modular framework for representing and applying ethical principles. In 16th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 96-104.

Bogomolnaia A., Jackson M. O. (2002). The stability of hedonic coalition structures. Games and Economic Behavior, vol. 38, no 2, p. 201–230.

Boissier O., Bonnet G., Cointe N., de Swarte T., Vallée T. (2018). Building ethical collectives. Rapport technique. ANR ETHICAA.

Boltanski L., Thévenot L. (2006). On justification: Economies of worth. Princeton University Press.

Brandl F., Brandt F., Strobel M. (2015). Fractional hedonic games: Individual and group stability. In 14th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 1219–1227.

Brey P. (2014). From moral agents to moral factors: the structural ethics approach. In P. Kroes, P.-P. Verbeek (Eds.), The moral status of technical artefacts, p. 125-142. Springer Netherlands. Brey P. (2015). International differences in ethical standards and in the interpretation of legal frameworks. Rapport technique. SATORI.

Bringsjord S., Taylors J. (2012). Introducing divine-command robot ethics. In P. Lin, G. Bekey, K. Abney (Eds.), Robot ethics: the ethical and social implication of robotics, p. 85-108. MIT Press.

Chamfort N. (1857). Maximes, pensées, anecdotes, caractères et dialogues. Durr.

Cointe N., Bonnet G., Boissier O. (2016). Ethical judgment of agents’ behaviors in multiagent systems. In 15th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 1106–1114.

Coleman K. (2001). Android arete: Toward a virtue ethic for computational agents. Ethics and Information Technology, vol. 3, no 4, p. 247-265.

Comte A. (1966). Catéchisme positiviste. Arnaud.

Dambra S. (2005). Durkheim et la notion de morale. Revue Interrogation, vol. 1.

DDHC. (1789). Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen de 1789 - Article 4.

Dennis L., Fisher M., Winfield A. (2015). Towards verifiably ethical robot behaviour. In 1st International Workshop on AI and Ethics, p. 45–52.

Dreze J. H., Greenberg J. (1980). Hedonic coalitions: Optimality and stability. Econometrica, vol. 48, no 4, p. 987–1003.

Durkheim E. (1893). De la division du travail social: étude sur l’organisation des sociétés supérieures. Alcan.

Durkheim E. (1897). Le suicide: étude de sociologie. Alcan.

Eckel C. C., Grossman P. J. (1996). Altruism in anonymous dictator games. Games and Economic Behavior, vol. 16, no 2, p. 181–191.

Elkind E., Wooldridge M. (2009). Hedonic coalition nets. In 8th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 417–424.

Endriss U. (2006). Monotonic concession protocols for multilateral negotiation. In 5th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 392–399.

Ganascia J. (2007). Modeling ethical rules of lying with answer set programming. Ethics and Information Technology, vol. 9, p. 39-47.

Gigerenzer G. (2010). Moral satisficing: Rethinking moral behavior as bounded rationality. Topics in Cognitive Science, vol. 2, no 3, p. 528-554.

Greenberg J. (1994). Coalition structures. In R. Aumann, S. Hart (Eds.), Handbook of game theory with economic applications (volume 2), p. 1305–1337. Elsevier.

Halpern J. Y. (2015). Cause, responsibility, and blame: a structural-model approach. Law, Probability, and Risk, vol. 14, no 2, p. 91–118.

Hoffman E., McCabe K., Smith V. L. (1996). Social distance and other-regarding behavior in dictator games. The American Economic Review, vol. 86, no 3, p. 653–660.

Hursthouse R. (2013). Virtue ethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Lorini E. (2012). On the logical foundations of moral agency. In 11th International Conference on Deontic Logic in Computer Science, p. 108-122.

Mill J. S. (1869). On liberty. Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer.

Mill J. S. (1889). L’utilitarisme. Alcan.

Montesquieu C.-L. d. S. de. (1867). Esprit des lois. Librairie de Firmon Didot Frères.

Morgenstern O., Von Neumann J. (1953). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton University Press.

Nash J. F. (1950). Equilibrium points in n-person games. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, vol. 36, no 1, p. 48–49.

Nongaillard A., Mathieu P. (2011). Reallocation problems in agent societies: a local mechanism to maximize social welfare. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, vol. 14, no 3, p. 5.

Onfray M. (2011). Manifeste hédoniste. Autrement.

Pereira L., Saptawijaya A. (2007). Modelling morality with prospective logic. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, vol. 4874, p. 99-111.

Peters D., Elkind E. (2015). Simple causes of complexity in hedonic games. In 14th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems, p. 617–623.

Platon. (1966). La République. Garnier Flammarion Paris (traduction G. Leroux).

Rand A. (1964). The virtue of selfishness. Penguin.

Rand A. (2005). The fountainhead. Penguin.

Rokeach M. (1973). The nature of human values. New York Free Press.

Saptawijaya A., Pereira L. (2014). Towards modeling morality computationally with logic programming. In 16th International Symposium on Practical Aspects of Declarative Languages, p. 104-119.

Schwartz S., BilskyW. (1990). Toward a theory of the universal content and structure of values: Extensions and cross cultural replications. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, vol. 58, p. 878-891.

Schwartz S. H. (2012). An overview of the Schwartz theory of basic values. Online Readings in Psychology and Culture, vol. 2, no 1, p. 11.

Sung S. C., Dimitrov D. (2007). On myopic stability concepts for hedonic games. Theory and Decision, vol. 62, no 1, p. 31–45.

Valette-Florence P., Odin Y., Vinais J. (1996). Analyse confirmatoire des domaines motivationnels de schwartz : Une application au domaine des media. Rapport technique. CERAG – Université Grenoble 2.

Vallée T., Bonnet G. (2017). Jeux de coalitions hédoniques à concepts de solution multiples. In 25es Journées Francophones sur les Systèmes Multi-Agents, p. 53–62.

Wiegel V., van den Berg J. (2009). Combining moral theory, modal logic and MAS to create well-behaving artificial agents. International Journal of Social Robotics, vol. 1, no 3, p. 233- 242.